I've enjoyed several of architect Christopher Alexander's other books, especially
A Pattern Language, and I've always been curious about his 4 volume magnum opus
The Nature of Order. So I was pretty excited when I found a (slightly) discounted copy of volume 1 at the used bookstore. Unfortunately, as so often happens with magnum opera, here he
jumps the shark. I got something out of reading it and I even share many aspects of the same vision. But his attempt to create a grand unified theory of everything is too long, too abstract, and too full of breathless insistence on its own profundity to make me want to read the other 3 volumes.
The basic idea is simple and lovely -- architecture is about bringing space to life. In retrospect, we can see this as a simple way of describing what the patterns in
A Pattern Language are meant to do. By paying attention to these simple functional patterns we can create spaces that are more pleasant to
live in because they respond to many natural human needs. The resulting spaces don't merely solve a particular problem but weave together a container or a
frame that contributes to our overall mood and vitality day after day. So the goal is to create spaces that create
more life, spaces that
amplify life instead of
disciplining it. This seems like a fine theory of architecture (and fits remarkably well with Cache's theory in
Earth Moves or Stewart Brand's discussion in
How Buildings Learn) that lets us clearly articulate some aspects of what's gone wrong with modern architecture. The fanciest postmodern facades routinely contain nothing more than a set of boxes, optimized for properties such as cost of construction or maximum workplace productivity, boxes which remain utterly indifferent to the actual experience of the human beings they discipline. At its worst, this 'architecture' actually aims to produce a space that
reduces the amount of life that can happen in it, and even at its best it assumes that life is something which can only be properly ascribed to the occupants of space, rather than the space itself, as if our outer context had nothing to do with our inner experience. Even quite high end contemporary architecture frequently produces these big neutral rooms that function like a
sack of space, a container fit for potatoes not people, and then dress this failure up in stylized features that look good in magazines. The real
art here lies not in the architecture, but in the sculpture or the photography, or perhaps simply the marketing. It frequently seems like we've forgotten that architecture is for
living in.
Alexander's goal, however, is not simply to define architecture, or critique other pretenders to the throne (although there is quite a lot of the latter here). He wants to systematically explore how to create spaces which are alive. Which brings us to the tricky question that occupies all of volume 1 -- what do me mean by life? With this book, Alexander tries to go well beyond the somewhat vague and intuitive way of posing this question that I've started with. He wants to literally define the life of a space in an 'objective' manner, as if the space itself had a sort of structural life inherent in its geometry, irrespective of the humans who might happen to occupy it. In fact, in some sense, Alexander's vision has no place in it for living humans per se, since in the end nothing exists for him but space itself. This would be the supposedly objective medium that nevertheless has a quasi-mystical capacity for arranging itself into subjects or, as Alexander terms them, "centers". These centers are not pre-existing entities, but arise as nodes in a field constituted by smaller centers. But then they also react back upon the smaller nodes that they unify, modifying those centers, and hence modifying themselves in a perpetual feedback loop. It's turtles both all the way up and all the way down. It's an empty non-dual world where all of space is alive to varying degree, and "life" is little more than a measure of the sort of "density of space" in a certain region. Thus when Alexander talks about architecture bringing a space to life, he means it literally -- architecture is the queen of the arts and sciences because it manipulates space directly, and the architect is a kind of god because they create life through this manipulation. Like I said, it's a theory of everything.
Setting aside the architectural hubris of it, I find the general idea quite attractive. It's very similar to Deleuze's idea of
folding, or Joanna Macy's
understanding of dependent origination as a form of systems theory, or Simondon's
crystallization schema for individuation. All of these are descriptions of the way something arises out of nothing in the manner of a vortex. And they all share an infinite recursive structure both in spatial and causal terms (what Macy calls
mutual causality). Insofar as I have a philosophy, this is pretty much it. So Alexander adds another metaphor we can use to think about how ontology works -- he thinks of it as the production of
centers. He also fleshes out an interesting list of 15 ways that centers can interact to amplify one another and even create new centers. I'm unclear how useful these would be for creating architecture in the colloquial sense (for those purposes, we might be better served by treating them as 15 categories that encompass his 253 pattern language), but they do provide food for thought. Perhaps in principle anything can happen in mutual causality, but in practice there do seem to be certain ontological patterns that frequently repeat.
Why then, if I like this vision, am I not going to read volumes 2-4? Ultimately, the problem isn't with Alexander's vision, but his articulation of it. While he endlessly insists on how this view of the world is profoundly different, he spends a lot of time trying ineffectively to justify it using the same old philosophical concepts of 'objectivity' and 'subjectivity' that it clearly explodes. So, for example, he spends forever telling us how life is an 'objective' property of a region of space that can measured mathematically. But this mathematics is pretty sketchy, which of course is hardly surprising given the complexity of the question and the recursive creativity of life. Having failed to convincingly calculated objective life, the text promptly pivots to assure us that the best test of life is actually the "mirror-of-self" test, a completely subjective measure that asks whether space A or space B is more like a "picture of our deepest self". We are to assume that this will somehow just naturally agree with the previous objective measure, even though we are simultaneously cautioned that it takes a lot of introspection to perform this test correctly. All of this risks legislating that what is 'natural' or 'living' is simply whatever Alexander likes. In fairness, he contends throughout that, at bottom, we all basically like the same stuff, or at least feel alive in the same spaces. And while I think there's a lot of truth in that, it's pretty clear it doesn't make for a scientific consensus. If I tell you that 75% of physicists think theory B is better, you'd hardly consider the matter settled, and yet Alexander seems routinely willing to dismiss this level of diversity of opinion about his own measures as due to people just not getting it. So ultimately the problem is that these elaborate justifications of his theory take up a lot of space and yet actually end up detracting from it for everyone. They won't change the mind of the 'hard-nosed' materialists who will remain unconvinced that the universe contains anything but marbles. And for those of us who have already joined the choir, they simply get in the way, muddy the point with amateur philosophy, and dilute what we can take from his ideas by spreading them out of four times as many pages as were required. I find I'm slowly becoming more curmudgeonly with long books -- if you can't say it in 150 pages, you probably don't know what's truly important to say, and if you find yourself talking for 1500 pages, something has clearly gone wrong. Don't give me your magnum opus that sums up everything. Give me a single idea worked to completion.